The book that I read this month is 'The Future of the Mind_ The Scientific Quest to Understand, Enhance, and Empower the Mind-Doubleday' Michio Kaku.
In
his book, “Physics of the Future,” Kaku took readers on a
whirlwind tour of science fictions he believes are poised to become
science realities: space travel and nanotech medical robots. In “The
Future of the Mind,” Kaku ushers us to even stranger territory — the
science of consciousness. Kaku claims the mysteries of the mind will
soon be mysteries no more. It’s an audacious assertion backed up, he
says, by a flood of new neuroscience technologies. But behind his
buoyant optimism lie questions that threaten the enterprise he describes
so skillfully. What does a science of the mind, rather than the brain,
look like? Does such a science require reducing the mind to “just
neurons,” or are there other paths to understanding the phenomena of
consciousness?
For
Kaku, the brain is a computer made of meat, and understanding the mind
is just a really, really hard engineering problem. The fundamental laws
are already known, and Kaku tells us we’ll soon be manipulating the
stuff of consciousness with the same acuity we push electrons around in
our digital devices. This singular confidence is both strength and
weakness as Kaku unspools his narrative, and doubts about his core
convictions begin to trail the reader like a parade of ghosts.
Kaku
takes us to laboratories where researchers are studying the microscopic
dynamics of the brain’s wiring. For example, using functional magnetic
resonance imaging (fMRI), which tracks neural activity, researchers have
recorded how the brain lights up when shown fragments of a video.
Scientists can then determine a subject’s neural response to seeing
various things. Comparing this dictionary of neural responses to the
observed fMRI patterns in a person viewing a different film, researchers
can reconstruct a reasonable facsimile of the film based purely on
brain activity. With this kind of technique it may even be possible for
scientists to crudely identify what people hooked to fMRI machines are
dreaming about.
From
these developments, Kaku imagines an era when memories can be recorded
and then played back into someone else’s head by stimulating the same
pattern of neural activity. Going one step further, machines wired
directly to brains will be able to read and transmit our thoughts
instantaneously.
Minds
made of meat (ours) are just one of Kaku’s concerns. He is also
interested in the possibilities of silicon and even alien minds. A
compelling chapter on artificial intelligence describes the explosion in
robotics and the new research that seeks to broaden the requirements
for silicon self-consciousness, including a capacity to feel emotion.
Like
the futurist Ray Kurzweil, Kaku believes the most important advances in
silicon computing will still serve our needs and not the coming robot
overlords (if we do create them). By mapping out the “connectome” — the
explicit account of every neural connection in your head — Kaku tells us
it should be possible to reverse-engineer each and every person’s
brain. Reconstruct this connectome in a computer and you will have
downloaded yourself into that machine. In this way the future of the
mind, your mind in particular, might last as long as there are computers
to run your connectome.
But
are you nothing more than the sum of your brain’s connections? Here’s
where Kaku stumbles. It’s been almost 20 years since the philosopher
David Chalmers introduced the distinction between “easy” and “hard”
problems in the study of consciousness. Easy problems, according to
Chalmers, were things like figuring out how the brain cycles through
signals from the arm allowing you to pick up an object. Researchers
developing the next generation of prosthetics will tell you this “easy”
problem remains pretty hard, but as Chalmers rightly pointed out,
control of the arm is nothing compared with developing a scientific
account of the vividness of our own experience. It’s the internal
luminosity — the “being” of our being — that constitutes Chalmers’s hard
problem and that eludes Kaku’s engineering-based perspective.
The
problem is that we still don’t have much in the way of a working model
of consciousness. With a physicist’s eye for economy, Kaku tries to
provide one through what he calls a “space-time theory.” It’s a model of
consciousness with a graded scale of awareness based on the number of
feedback loops between environment and organism. Thus, in Kaku’s view, a
thermostat has the lowest possible level of consciousness while humans,
with our ability to move through space and project ourselves mentally
backward and forward in time, represent the highest level currently
known.
I’ve
spent most of my professional life running supercomputer simulations of
events like the collapsing of interstellar gas clouds to form new
stars, and it seems to me that Kaku has taken a metaphor and mistaken it
for a mechanism. There has always been the temptation to take the
latest technology, like clockworks in the 17th century, and see it as a
model for the mechanics of thought. But simulations are not a self, and
information is not experience. Kaku acknowledges the existence of the
hard problem but waves it away. “There is no such thing as the Hard
Problem,” he writes.
Thus
the essential mystery of our lives — the strange sense of presence to
which we’re bound till death and that lies at the heart of so much
poetry, art and music — is dismissed as a non-problem when it’s exactly
the problem we can’t ignore. If we’re to have anything like a final
theory of consciousness, we had better be attentive to the complexity of
how we experience our being.
When
Kaku quotes the cognitive scientist Marvin Minsky telling us that
“minds are simply what brains do,” he assumes that scientific accounts
of consciousness must reduce to discussions of circuitry and programming
alone. But there are other options. For those pursuing ideas of
“emergence,” descriptions of lower-level structures, like neurons, don’t
exhaust nature’s creative potential. There’s also the more radical
possibility that some rudimentary form of consciousness must be added to
the list of things the world is built of, like mass or electric charge.
On
the ethical front, Kaku does an admirable job of at least raising the
troubling issues inherent in the technologies he describes, but there’s
one critical question he misses entirely. The deployment of new
technologies tends to create their own realities and values. If we treat
minds like meat-computers, we may end up in a world where that’s the
only aspect of their nature we perceive or value.
Keeping
these questions in mind, however, only enhances the enjoyment of this
wide-ranging book. Kaku thinks with great breadth, and the vistas he
presents us are worth the trip even if some of them turn out to be only
dreamscapes.
THE FUTURE OF THE MIND
The Scientific Quest to Understand, Enhance, and Empower the Mind
By Michio Kaku
Aucun commentaire:
Enregistrer un commentaire